On Dependency between Wishes and Perception
https://doi.org/10.32603/2412-8562-2021-7-6-17-27
Abstract
Introduction. Empirical studies of recent years convincingly show that the character of sensory perception can be influenced by non-cognitive mental states of the agent, such as her desires. The aim of the paper is to analyze how this causal connection between agent's wishes and her sensations can affect the epistemological status of dependent sensations.
Methodology and sources. The author examines S. Siegel's argument on this issue. S. Siegel argues that the empirically proven dependence of sensations on desires (wishful seeing) should lead to a decrease of the epistemological status of sensations to the same extent as the dependence of beliefs on desires (wishful thinking) leads to a decrease of the epistemological status of these beliefs. Thus Siegel's argument concludes that the phenomenon of wishful seeing deprives us of any reason to accept sensations as credible evidence of the states of the world. So, this is an argument in favor of skepticism.
Results and discussion. The article discusses two main strategies for rejecting Siegel's argument. According to the first strategy proposed by R. Long, sensations are not so similar to beliefs that one can conclude that their epistemological status should be decreased on the basis of their dependence on desires. According to another strategy for refuting Siegel's argument, proposed by A. Raftopoulos, the influence of desires on perception does not extend to early vision. Early vision is free from the influence of higher order conscious mental states. The dependence of the results of sensory perception on other mental states is reduced to the influence of these states on the agent's attention. At the same time, attention can be volitionally controlled and can be trained. Therefore dependent perception under certain conditions can be rationally accepted.
Conclusion. Thus, the article shows that, even though perception is dependent on other non-cognitive mental states, such as desires, this dependence does not necessarily lead to a decrease in the epistemological status of sensations, so sensations can be rationally accepted under certain conditions. This means that Siegel's argument for skepticism is not compelling.
Keywords
About the Authors
A. I. PonomarevRussian Federation
Andrei I. Ponomarev – Assistant Lecturer at the Department of Philosophy
5 Professor Popov str., St Petersburg 197376, Russia
K. G. Frolov
Russian Federation
Konstantin G. Frolov – Research Officer at the Department of Philosophy; Can. Sci. (Philosophy) (2017), Research Officer at the International Laboratory for Logic, Linguistics and Formal Philosophy
5 Professor Popov str., St Petersburg 197376, Russia
11 Pokrovsky blvd., Moscow 109028, Russia
References
1. Hansen, T., Olkkonen, M., Walter, S. and Gegenfurtner, K.R. (2006), “Memory Modulates Color Appearance”, Nature Neuroscience, vol. 9, iss. 11, pp. 1367–1368. DOI: 10.1038/nn1794.
2. Levin, D.T. and Banaji, M.R. (2006), “Distortions in the Perceived Lightness of Faces: The Role of Race Categories”, J. of Experimental Psychology: General, vol. 135, no. 4, pp. 501–512. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1037/0096-3445.135.4.501.
3. Payne, K. (2001), “Prejudice and Perception: The Role of Automatic and Controlled Processes in Misperceiving a Weapon”, J. of Personality and Social Psychology, vol. 81, no. 2, pp. 181–192. DOI: 10.1037/0022-3514.81.2.181.
4. Siegel, S. (2017), “How is Wishful Seeing Like Wishful Thinking?”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, vol. 95, iss. 2, pp. 408–435. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12273.
5. Long, R. (2018), “How Wishful Seeing is not Like Wishful Thinking”, Philosophical Studies, vol. 175, iss. 6, pp. 1401–1421. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0917-2.
6. Raftopoulos, A. (2015), “The Cognitive Impenetrability of Perception and Theory-ladenness”, J. for General Philosophy of Science, vol. 46, iss. 1, pp. 87–103. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-015-9288-6.
7. McGrath, M. (2013), “Siegel and the Impact for Epistemological Internalism”, Philosophical Studies, vol. 162, iss. 3, pp. 723–732. DOI: 10.1007/s11098-012-0055-9.
8. Lewis, D. (1980), “Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision”, Australasian J. of Philosophy, vol. 58, no. 3, pp. 239–249. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/00048408012341251.
9. Chernyak, A.Z. (2020), “Knowledge and Luck”, Epistemology & Philosophy of Science, vol. 57, no. 2, pp. 61–78. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202057222.
10. Baumann, P. (2014), “No Luck with Knowledge? On a Dogma of Epistemology”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, vol. 89, iss. 3, pp. 523–551. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2012.00622.x.
11. Frankfurt, H.G. (1969), “Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility”, The J. of Philosophy, vol. 66, iss. 23, pp. 829–839. DOI: 10.2307/2023833.
12. Marchi, F. (2020), “The Epistemic Role of Early Vision: Cognitive Penetration and Attentional Selection”, Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia, vol. 11, no. 3, pp. 385–396. DOI: https://doi.org/ 10.4453/rifp.2020.0027.
Review
For citations:
Ponomarev A.I., Frolov K.G. On Dependency between Wishes and Perception. Discourse. 2021;7(6):17-27. (In Russ.) https://doi.org/10.32603/2412-8562-2021-7-6-17-27